Section 124 A, under which I am happily charged, is perhaps the prince among the political sections of the Indian Penal Code designed to suppress the liberty of the citizen. – (Mahatma Gandhi, March 18, 1922.)
In this course, we have been examining freedom of speech and various legal restrictions upon this fundamental right. Sedition, (in particular as embodied in Section 124 A of the Indian Penal Code) is one such restriction.
The rationale for sedition is based on the principle that dissemination of seditious material
undermines the loyalty of citizens, that disloyal citizens jeopardise the Government at Law, and that a weakened Government at Law threatens the very fabric of the state as well as public order and safety.
Thus, the various judicial justifications for the law of sedition conglomerate around invocations of the necessity for preserving the Government, without questioning whether the Government in fact is something worth protecting. Certainly many believed that in the context of British India, it was not. According to Gandhi, “…I hold it as a virtue to be disaffected towards a Government, which
in its totality has done more harm to India than any previous system.” The import of the present law of sedition cannot be abstracted from its historical context in colonial rule. The law of sedition is the unfortunate legacy of the British Government in India. Pre-independence, it was a mechanism employed by the courts to quash anti-government sentiment, by stemming the propagation of ideas that might (either did or were intended to) cause the listeners to feel “disaffection” for the Government of British India. It is for this reason that Mohandas Gandhi called 124A, the “prince” amongst mechanisms used to silence political opposition.
Certainly, the repressive implementation of 124A casts a long shadow. Today, the law still stands (though as we shall see with a modified interpretation at common law.) The recent wave of cases against writers, editors, politicians, lawyers, human rights activists, political activists and public intellectuals is demonstrative of the broad application of the statute. Many of those arrested
have been high profile and respected figures, locally and nationally, such as Binayak Sen, who is the subject of a case study below.
3. DOCTRINAL DEVELOPMENTS (EVOLUTION OF THE LAW)
There are two ways in which one may be guilty of sedition. One must either actually incite the disaffection or have attempted to incite the disaffection. Either are sufficient for guilt. In the later case, it is not of any relevance that the audience did not feel any disaffection.
Pre-Independence, 124A remained much the same as at its inception, with minor amendments, which were predominantly for the sake of clarifying and unifying the way that it had been interpreted at common law.
Much discussion has centred on the meaning of the term “disaffection.” In the Bose Case, the judges interpreted it as merely the opposite to affection. But later it was held to be a positive feeling, not just the absence of affection Justice Strachey took a particularly broad approach in his definition of disaffection as “hatred, enmity, dislike, hostility, contempt and every form of ill-
will” to the Government. In Bashkir Balavant Bopatkar1906, disaffection was interpreted not as a feeling for another individual, but a feeling one had for a ruler.
Disaffection is however distinguished from disapprobation. The second and third explanation of S124A says that comments expressing disapprobation of “the measures” or of the “administrative or other actions” of the Government which do not excite disaffection are not seditious under the act.
Disaffection or Violent Consequences
There is a distinct difference between someone who incites disaffection and one who incites violence. The latter is a consequentialist approach, which shifts the focus away from the feeling of the audience, to what they will do or what they might do.
In 1942, the Federal Court in Niharendu Dutt Majumar held that “the acts or words complained of must either incite to disorder or must be such to satisfy reasonable men that that is there intention,” (My emphais).This was a break from the emphasis on the feeling incited, to the potential consequence of that feeling; that is disorder. In effect, this is (can be read as) an acknowledgement that the domain of the courts is not “the thoughts of the heart.”
However, this rendering of sedition was overturned by the Privy Council in the Sadashiv Case, marking a return to the traditional interpretation. They returned to Justices Stachey’s interpretation in the first Tilak case. Here he said, “(t)he offence consists in exiting or attempting to excite in others certain bad feelings towards the Government. It is not the exciting or attempting to excite mutiny or
rebellion, or any sort of actual disturbance, great or small,” (My emphasis).
Clearly, the issue was not incitement to violence but incitement to feelings of disaffection. Intending to excite bad feelings and intending to excite rebellion are not always co-extensive. One may incite disaffection with the intention of bringing about peaceful change. Likewise one may incite disorder with no intention as to the audience’s state of mind. If we take seriously the liberalist “harm principle,” as posited by the philosopher John Stuart Mill, then it is only the harm of violence, which can justify the curtailment of free speech.
Omission from the Constitution
During the drafting of the Constitution, much discussion occurred over whether the term “sedition” should be included as a restriction upon the right to free speech, (finally article 19 (2).) K.M Munshi, a lawyer and activist for the Indian Independence Movement, argued that it should not be included because of the way in which sedition has been used as a mechanism of state oppression; its “curious fortune.” “Our notorious Section 124A of the Penal Code,” he explained “was sometimes construed so widely that I remember in a case a criticism of the District Magistrate was urged to be covered by Section 124A.”
Several years later, the decision not to include the term “sedition” was discussed by Justice Fazl Ali:
The framers of the constitution must have therefore found themselves face to face with the dilemma as to whether the word “sedition” should be used in article 19(2) and if it was to be used in what sense it was to be used. On the one hand, they must have had before their mind the very widely accepted view supported by numerous authorities that sedition was essentially an offence against public tranquillity and was connected in some way with public disorder; and on the other hand, there was the pronouncement of the Judicial Committee that sedition as defined in the Indian Penal Code did not necessarily imply any intention or tendency to incite disorder. In these circumstances, it is not surprising that they decided not to use the word “sedition” in clause (2) but used the more general words, which cover sedition and everything else which make sedition such a serious offence. That sedition does undermine the security of the State is a matter which cannot admit of much doubt. That
it undermines the security of the State usually through the medium of public disorder is also a matter on which eminent Judges and jurists are agreed. Therefore, it is difficult to hold that public disorder or disturbance of public tranquillity are not matters which undermine the security of the
State.
Thus, because of the connotational baggage of the term “sedition,” it was finally omitted from Art 19(1)(a) of the Indian Constitution. This marks both the condemnation for the way in which the sedition laws had hitherto been employed and expressed a desire to break with the oppressive colonialist means of managing dissent and disobedience.
However, his break was largely symbolic because the laws under which sedition operated were still firmly in place. Unconstitutional and Inappropriate Article 13 (1) of the Indian Constitution renders void any law which is incompatible with the Constitution. The sedition law, if in conflict with Art 19 of the Constitution would be invalid. A number of cases in the 1950 probe the question of constitutional compatibility. This question remained even after the constitutional amendment in 1951, which added public order to the list of factors that could legitimately restrict freedom of speech.
In the case of Tara Singh Gopi Chand v The State,34 Chief Justice Eric Weston explained the irrelevance of 124A, in the contemporary political setting. India is now a sovereign democratic state. Governments may go and be caused to go without the foundations of the state being impaired. A law
of sedition thought necessary during a period of foreign rule has become inappropriate by the very nature of the change, which has come about.
The flexibility and resilience of an independent democracy meant that it should not only withstand but should thrive upon fervent critique and disagreement, which is the fruit of a plurality of voices. Eric Weston CJ concluded that, “the section then must be held void.” Such sentiment is reflective of K.M Munshi.
As a matter of fact the essence of democracy is criticism of Government. The party system which necessarily involves an advocacy of the replacement of one Government by another is its only bulwark; the advocacy of a different system of Government should be welcome because that gives vitality to a democracy.
Eight years later, this position was again furthered in two cases. One was that of Sabir Raza, whereby criticisms of the Chief Minister of Utter Pradesh was held not to amount to sedition. In Ram Nandan’s case, the High Court of Allahabad overturned the conviction of Ram Nandan for a speech he made to a group of villagers. Section 124A was again held to be unconstitutional. Justice Gurtu
explained that it was possible for people who legitimately and peaceably criticise the government to be caught in “the mischief of Section 124A of the Indian Penal Code.” For this reason he said it should be invalidated.
These progressive decisions were overturned by the Supreme Court in KedarNath Sing v State of Bihar. Whilst the court upheld the constitutionality of
the law of sedition they reinterpreted its meaning, as discussed above.
4. COMPARATIVE LAW
Whilst there are many countries that still have sedition laws, the general trend is certainly away from such laws, which are often remnants of colonial era political landscapes. In some jurisdictions, sedition has been repelled altogether. Where they remain these laws are not uncontroversial or uncontested, brushing up against national constitutions and human rights frameworks. In some cases, the scope of the law has been narrowed to a minimalist construction, prosecutions are rare, and punishments are often nominal. This next section is a brief outline of some of the contemporary approaches internationally to sedition.
United Kingdom
In the UK, Seditious libel was abolished under the Coroners and Justice Act 2010. This abolition the consequence of the laws contravention of the UK’s Human Rights Act 1998 and the underlying rights of the European Convention on Human Rights which the HRA upheld. Prior to this however, the law was rarely engaged and the rule under ex parte Choudhury restricted the application of seditious
libel to cases where there was a provocation to violence.
However, the protection awarded by the ECHR does not extend to non-European nationals. In addition, the Terrorism Act of 2000 includes offenses such as “inciting terrorist acts” and “providing training for terrorist purposes at home or overseas.”
New Zealand
In New Zealand sedition was abolished in 2007, under the Crimes (Repeal of Seditious Offences) Amendment Act 2007. It was understood that the criminalisation of dissenting views was not a useful or appropriate response, that itcontravened the New Zealand Bill of Rights and that sedition in New Zealand bore a ‘”tainted history”. The New Zealand parliament also noted the vagueness of sedition, its irrelevance in the contemporary context, the appropriateness of other criminal law provisions to deal with cases of incitement to violence and importantly, the “chilling effect” that such laws have upon free speech.
USA
In the USA, under Brandenburgv Ohio, the court said that advocating a doctrine of violence in abstract terms was not considered sedition, whereas advocating immediate violence was. The prior, it was held was protected by the First Amendment and the distinction was the immediacy of the threat. This law operates under civil jurisdiction and there is a separate code governing military justice where both sedition and failure to supress sedition is punishable under a court marshal.
Nigeria
In Choke Obi, the Nigerian laws on sedition were found to be constitutional. Criticism of the Government, insofar as it was a“malignant matter,” was seditious. Subsequent cases such as Nwankwohave challenged this ruling on the grounds that sedition is incompatible with free speech. The matter is not finally settled but some scholars, such as F.C. Nwoke, suggest that as the former
was decided under colonial rule, the latter is more authoritative. Australia
In Australia, Sedition laws are codified under some states criminal codes and the federal Anti-Terrorism Act 2005, which replaced the references to sedition in the Federal Crimes Act 1914. Prior to 2005, the last conviction of sedition had been in 1961.
Malaysia
In Malaysia, sedition is governed under the Sedition Act 1948, which criminalises one who “does or attempts to do, or makes any preparation to do, or conspires with any person to do”, acts or speaks or prints words which have a seditious tendency. In addition, the act covers any person who has seditious material in their possession, without lawful excuse. The stringency of these laws are considered reasonable restrictions on Art 10(1) of the Malaysian Constitution dealing with free speech. The sedition laws in Malaysia are currently undergoing a process of governmental review.
5. THE AFFECTIVE TURN – THE AFFECT OF THE LAW
In this section, we will be examining the affect of the law and of media constructions of the law. Our concern here is how the laws, the rhetoric that judges and writers employ and the implementation of the law impacts upon the wider society. This can be divided into three sections.
A). The legal mechanisms of fear of persecution and prosecution.
B). The moral panic created by the institutions of law and the media.
C). Manufacturing patriotism and affection
We shall see how, these three points are used to thematise sites of struggle, which gravitate around the law of sedition. a. Law as a mechanism for generating the fear of prosecution and persecution.
There are a plethora of mechanisms that governments can take advantage of to silence resistance amongst the population. Traditional forms of censorship, prohibition of publications, confiscation of printing presses, punishment of violators such as imprisonment, fines or deportation are some of the more obvious legal means. Limitations over the avenues through which dissent and alternate voices can be legitimately issued are another way. According to Dhavan, this approach as traditionally employed in India, helped to steer the emerging polity towards a “government by institution” by
insisting that only acceptable form of influence on governments had to come through the properly designated institutional and social channels.
However, the more covert means is the psychological pressure – the threat of sanctions and indeed of the trial itself – which encourages self-censorship amongst the population. The over use (and misuse) of S 124A in recent times can perhaps be viewed as means of reinforcing this threat, a method of silencing not just the transgressor, but signalling to the wider population the very real
possibility of prosecution. The former Attorney-General, Soli Sorabjee, touches upon this fear when he suggested that the spate of arrests have invited “an atmosphere of paranoia.”
Justice Holmes in his dissenting judgement in Gitlow v People of New York said that, “(e)very idea is an incitement. The only difference between the expression of opinion and an incitement in the narrower sense is the speaker’s enthusiasm for the result.” If this is the case also in Indian law, then those with opinions which run counter to the dominate discourse, should be careful about how much
enthusiasm they speak with.
b. The law and the media as generating moral panics.
Lord Mansfield drew an analogy in 1784 when he said that a licentious press was like a Pandora’s box and that it was “the source of every evil.” In India, the law also uses the fear of the consequences of free speech to justify restrictions. The courts utilise the fear of rebellion, of social unrest and of the dire consequence to national order that permitting seditious material would unleash. This moral
panic is predominantly directed against various political and religious organisations.
The “threat” that such associations pose to the Indian government is real, even if it is wholly manufactured. If the dreaded eventuality comes to pass, then this substantiates the threat; if it does not, then it is because the enemy “would have if they could have” but the countermeasures proved effective. Once generated, the threat to society is existent in its potentiality. The threat is real insofar as its affect is felt in us beings. It breathes through the fear of the public. It is thus embodied, not abstract. But this paradigm can be reversed. The higher courts, liberally inclined political orators, human rights advocates and the sections of the English speaking press employ a similar discourse of threat against the law of sedition. According to them, it is the law itself that poses the greatest threat to our society and our way of life, by chipping away at fundamental freedoms and encroaching on
democratic rights. This converts tolerance into a positive ideology in itself. When Evelyn Beatrice Hall paraphrased Voltaire as saying, “I disapprove of what you say, but I will defend to the death your right to say it,” she articulated concisely this liberalist position.
c. Manufacturing patriotism
Affection can not be manufactured or regulated by the law. If one has no affection for a person, one should be free to give the fullest expression to his disaffection, so long as he does not contemplate, promote or incite to violence. (Mahatma Gandhi, March 18, 1922.)
However, affection can be manufactured. A good way to do it is though institutionalised protection of fundamental freedoms that people value. Another is to present the government in the role of defender of those freedoms, rather than a force which steals them in the night. The Government can better generate affection by using the carrot, rather than the stick.
Justice Holmes and Justice Brandeis were both proponents of the “marketplace of ideas.” The “marketplace of ideas” is an economic metaphor by which more free speech can never be a bad thing. In the same way that minimal state intervention into market forces is to be valued, so is minimal state obstruction of the First Amendment rights. They advocated their staunch application of the right
to free speech on the grounds that is was essential to the maintenance of
government, and not a threat to it. Such sentiment is echoed in the Nigerian case of State v Ivory Trumpet Publishing Company Limited where the court held that, in fact, a thick culture of
free speech was, rather than detrimental to the stability of the state, essential to it.
The greater the importance of safeguarding the community from incitements to the overthrow of our institutions by force, the more imperative is the need to preserve inviolate the constitutional rights of free speech, free press and free assembly in order to maintain the opportunity for free political discussion, to the end that government may be responsible to the will of the people and that changes, if desired, may be obtained by peaceful means. Therein lies the security of the Republic, the very foundation of Constitutional Government.
If ones aim is to nurture patriotism, such rhetoric seems to be a far more effective tool than the implementation of oppressive laws.
6. TWO CASE STUDIES
a. Binayak Sen
In the well-published case of Dr. Binayak Sen, the General Secretary of the Peoples Union for Civil Liberties, was arrested under Section 124A of the IPC, under Section 121A of the IPC and under state law, The Chhattisgarh Special Public Security Act 2005. Binayak was charged with conspiring with
Narayan Sanyal and Piyush Guha against the Indian Government. It was claimed that he passed letters onto Narayan Sanyal, who was himself arrested in possession of Naxalite literature.
Dr Sen provided healthcare to the Adivasis in remote areas of Chhattisgarh. He was also involved in organising fact-finding campaigns into human rights violations in the region, including murders, deaths in custody and deaths from malnutrition. Civil rights organisations have presented the arrest (and later conviction) as an articulated retaliation for Sen’s human rights work, in particular the uncovering of the atrocities of the Salwa Judum in Dantewada and the police’s involvement in this.Sen is vocal critic of the Government programme of arming villagers to suppress the Naxal insurgency in the state.
Most of the reports in the English media frame the conviction as politically motivated. Some reports have said that the arrest, as a government strategy for silencing dissent has backfired; that it has worked to draw attention to the draconian sedition and state level laws. This is particularly so since Dr Sen won the prestigious Jonathan Mann Award for Global Health and Human Rights, and
after a letter was delivered to the Prime-Minister calling for Sen’s release and signed by twenty-two Nobel Prize Winners.
b. Koondankulam protests
Another application of the sedition laws has been mass arrests of protesters in Idinthakarai and Koodankulam in Tamil Nadu. Amidst protests over the safety of the Koondankulam power plant, the police have arrested up to 6000 people in the months from September to December 2011 alone. They have been charged with sedition (under Section124A) and waging war against the Government (under Section 121) of the Indian Penal Code. Police officials say that the figures are inflated and that there is no doctrine of harassment.
The arrested include political activists including those from The Peoples Movement Against Nuclear Energy (PMANE), and large numbers local villagers and fishermen who will be affected by the plant’s opening. Some media reports have said that the use of sedition laws, rather than for example, terrorism laws, is a strategic practice to impose sanction and an atmosphere of fear in the region, without drawing unwanted media attention to the protests.
Dr. Udayakumar, a representative of the PMANE has made claims that the power plant is unsafe, challenging the lack of consultation with the public and lack of transparency of the process. He was reported as saying that “It’s an authoritarian project that has been imposed on the people.” Udayakumar also said that he has declined to participate in some further talks, for the fear that he may be arrested. This is illustrative of the use of fear to silence protesters voices and to stop the open discussion of issues regarding the health of the local population and environmental welfare.
No responses yet